Thursday, April 30, 2015

On the Nature of Thought (HM 1.1)

What did Aristotle mean when he asked the question:  What is the correct way to think?

Contrary to what is usually the first concluded answer, Aristotle cared very little about what biases you had in your life that cause you to think one way or the other.  Instead, Aristotle was questioning the method of existence in logic, epistemology, which then carries over into how to think logically about existence.  Aristotle's famous three laws are as follows:

1) The Law of Identity:  Each existence is identical with itself  (A is A)
2) Law of Noncontradiction:  Each existence is not different from itself (A is not non-A)
3) Law of Excluded Middle:  No existence can be both itself and different from itself (Any X is either A or non-A, but not both at once).

It should be clear that the foundation of existence for Aristotle is self-identifying reification (recognition of the self).  This can be credited to his teacher and primary influence, Plato.  His laws make the same point from three different angles: Positively, it says that a thing can only be what it is.  Negatively, it says that a thing cannot be what it is not.  Dichotomously, it says that there are only two alternatives:  A or non-A.

Most of these perspectives we see as general 'truisms', meaning that they are commonly accepted as facts of existence.  They can be summed up by Descartes' "I think therefore I am."  In Descartes' simple sentence he places thought prior to existence.  It is thus only through the identification of the self that the self can claim its existence.

The historical materialist however, points out that these so-called 'truisms' are held chiefly because they are reproduced regularly by society's educational system as the standard way of thinking about existence.  As this note hopes to show, Aristotle's view is not necessarily false...but it is rather oversimplified.

Let us start with what John Somerville used to explain the breakdown in Aristotle's logic, a piece of paper.  According to Aristotelian logic, the paper is paper (A is A); it is not different from paper (A is not non-A); and anything that exists must either be paper or not be paper (and X is either A or non-A, but not both).  However, if we watch the paper's existence over a long period of time we are forced to question whether or not Aristotle was in fact correct.  We know, just by scientific reasoning, that after thousands of years...even if the paper was isolated from interaction....it would be very different from what it is now; in fact it might not even be paper anymore.

The paper would have changed chemically and physically to such an extent that it would literally become something else than it originally was.  As Somerville said, it would "crumble into dust."  The point to get here is that everything is constantly becoming something else, and thus Aristotle's first law is overly simplistic in its assertion about the primacy of something's existence.  For if one were to seriously ask "at what point does the paper cease to be paper and become something else?" the answer would be:  Constantly.  More importantly, the more we examine a particular object, like paper, we are forced to the conclusion that not only are changes always taking place, but that changes are taking place throughout all parts of the object in question.

Scientific examinations helps to explain this further.  Quantum dynamism and contemporary physics tells us that the paper is in fact made up of mostly "empty space" in which a series of billions of particles are spinning and interacting with one another, held together within a electromagnetic field.  As Somerville points out, "the empty space itself must not be thought of as nothingness...but as a field possessed with definite properties.  All these things and events--the billions of highly activated particles, the field that has specific effects on them, the positive and negative forces at work which defines the field, the opposing combinations of units pushing and pulling in different directions....all of this is not something that takes place *ON* the paper.....it **IS** the paper."

The simplification of Aristotle's first law derives from its neglect of the concept of "rate of change."  When the "total rate" of the paper's existence is not too long...say....one minute to 10 years.....the paper is usable as paper and can be further used as paper.  These are only SOME of the factors that are important in understanding the paradoxical but pervasive dynamics whereby each thing is busy changing itself; is in a process of becoming something else 24-hours a day, non-stop.

The historical materialist holds that in a universe such as this, where units are constantly shifting from one state of existence to the next, the basic rules of correct thinking should reflect the basic situation of change.  This is not a method of thinking where the static and changeless take center position in thought while change plays a secondary role.  Rather it is one in which change is the essence and the core of existence, while it is the static "stabilities" that are merely passing and temporary.  "The process whereby each thing is changing its identity is primary, continuous and absolute; it is the identities reached that are secondary, temporary, and relative."

Thus the historical materialist has a new set of laws from which to derive the ontological question of "what is correct thinking?"

1) The Law of Strife, Interpenetration, and Unity of Opposites.  (A is A, and it is also non-A)

The reason each thing is in a constant process of growth and change is that each particular "thing" is made up of opposing forces and different interacting elements.  Simply, these are called "opposites" but the traditional Marxist or Dialectician will refer to them as "antitheses".  These different forces and opposing elements do not exist side by side, "like neighbors each of whom goes his own way without having any vital relationships to the other.  If that were the case, no complex "thing" would be formed that we would be likely to identify with a name, no 'unity' of elements would emerge."  Rather these opposing forces form a tight knit that balances together and "maintains itself as a pattern for a sufficient period of time to be distinguishable" from other "things".  THIS...is what accounts for the fact that every "thing" has a history.

The crude materialist however would reject that such a notion of existence applies to ideas.  Ideas, to the crudely undialectical materialist, represent nothing more than abstracted fantasies of material existence.  To combat this, let us again use Somerville's explanation with reference to "constitutionality":
"There is, indeed, one set of actual facts, one state of affairs that is objectively and absolutely the case in all fields. But there are different and competing theories, conceptions, and laws, all derived from ideas, offered in a continuing effort to explain these facts.

People ordinarily think of ideas as an isolated unit. But quickly it can be realized upon reflection that this unit is made up of different elements, interrelated in a certain way. In fact, the very definition of an idea is a statement of some of the chief elements and types of relationship present. Let us take the following idea of constitutionality as a supposed 'absolute idea.'

Let us use the following definition of constitutionality: the logical compatibility of a law or an action with the provisions of a constitution. We see at once that this idea would not...indeed it could not...exist except as a combination of elements, which are themselves other ideas, or aspects of other ideas.

In other words, if we did not understand the idea of logical compatibility, that of law, and that of a constitution itself, we would not be able to understand the idea of constitutionality...just as..if we could not physically identify hydrogen and oxygen, we would not be able to put them together in a certain proportion in order to produce water. Every idea has a specific ***content*** as an idea, quite apart from the fact that ideas also represent abstractions from material things.

Formal Logic, established by Aristotle, tells us that while we may move from one idea to another, ideas themselves are static...like the primary aspects of reality. This is essentially the same view as that taken of biological species prior to Darwin's work: the species exist side by side, but all are fixed; none grew out of others.

The dialectician thus holds that there is no reason for taking this view in the case of ideas when a view of this kind is taken in one field, it influences and encourages the taking of it in another. In any case, he points to the fact that such ideas as "logical compatibility", "law", and "constitution" undergo radical changes during the course of time; and he maintains that it is better, in a scientific sense, to explain a process of this kind as a growth or evolution than to deal with it as an unexplained transition between unalterable and unconnected absolute static entities."
In short, the first law of thought in historical materialism is a generalization, the point of which is to sum up change as the common basis to every level of existence.

If the first law identifies that everything that exists has a history that can be traced, thus revealing quantitative changes, the second law expressed that history is not only quantitative, but also qualitative.

2) The Law of Transition from Quantity to Quality (A becomes non-A, which then redefines A)

We can understand this law by simply referring to quantitative and qualitative changes in a single thing:  water.  When we increase the temperature of water, within certain limitations, we see a quantitative change.  The water remains water:  but it becomes a hotter liquid; it's particles moving at faster rates.  If however, this quantitative change continues...that is...if the temperature continues to be raised...a transition to a gaseous state occurs and a new qualitative condition emerges.  Steam is not simply water that is hotter than it was before; it has new definite properties that are not possessed by the liquid water.  Likewise, if the temperature is lowered beyond a certain point, another qualitative change takes place, this time into a solid.  Again:  The chemical properties of ice are not merely an "increased" or "decreased" degree in the properties of the liquid water; as a solid....ice contains chemical properties that water does not.

In other words, what this law is saying is that every accumulation of quantitative changes must eventually lead to some qualitative shift.  The old qualities are transformed into new ones.  It is also suggesting that the only means for producing these qualitative changes are shifts in the quantitative changes of the old qualities.  Thus history is not a simple "one-dimensional program" in which late developments can simply be "reduced" to earlier qualitative states.  The new qualitative differences contain within themselves new internal contradictions; new "opposites", new "antitheses", and new "quantitative rates of change".

3) The Law of the Negation of the Negation (A is constantly being redefined)This law requires somewhat of a more lengthy description, which will be found in HM 101.3.  For now, it is best to summarize the first two rules and how the third affects them both.  The first rule highlights that everything has a history.  The second rule emphasizes that this history is based upon a transition in quantitative conditions to qualitative ones.  The third rule, in a basic summation, emphasizes that the history established by Rule (1) and described by Rule (2)...never ends.  History does not stop.  Time does not stop.  Thus the only constant, is change.



Historical Materialism 101.1:  On the Nature of Thought.

By Joshua Morris.   Heavily Influenced by John Somerville's "The Philosophy of Dialectical Materialism"

No comments:

Post a Comment