Friday, May 1, 2015

Exploitation: The Roots of the Modern World System



 Abstract:  This short essay was written as a stream of consciousness back while rigorously studying Marx's "Wage Labor and Capital."  This segment was part of Robert Tucker's essential guide to historical materialism.  I tried to mix in Marx's assessment with more contemporary understandings of world-systems.  Enjoy.

----

                It is with no small amount of irony that throughout the 19th, 20th, and early 21st centuries the verbs to exploit and to capitalize on share virtually the same meaning.  The concept of exploitation extends far back before the 19th century, but following the publications of Karl Marx in the 2nd and 3rd quarters of the century, the concept took on a more direct and commonplace meaning.  But just what exactly does exploitation mean?  How are people exploited by a system in which they are both born into and dependent upon?  To what extent does exploitation relate to servitude?  The most essential answer to these questions is also the most basic:  exploitation occurs specifically in one realm of social existence, the workplace.  All other forms of exploitation are in many ways extensions of this specific and rooted antagonism between the employer and the employee.
                In his 1847 lectures on Wage Labor and Capital, Marx presented the “economic relations” that “constitute[d] the material foundation of the present class struggles and national struggles.”[1]  In order to understand these struggles in both their economic (class) and national forms, the formal presentation of the relationship between the antagonistic groups is necessary.  For Marx, these relations expose an internal contradiction between the relationships, which are portrayed as equal due to the exchange of one service (labor) for a value (payment, money, means of subsistence; wage).  In order to try and break down the illusion of equality between the exchange, Marx asks the direct question:  “What are wages?”  In referring to the position of the worker, wages and payments are those paid by an employer (capitalist) “for a particular labour time or for a particular output of labour.”[2]  The employer thus buys labor-power, whereas the laborer sells labor power.  In this way, the exchange is laid out as a transaction, and “labour power” becomes itself a commodity in the same way that any item that is produced and sold is also a commodity.
                Marx’s next question refers to the purpose of this transaction altogether:  Why does the laborer sell his labor?  The answer is given as “in order to live.”  Straightforward as this may seem to the average reader, Marx flips the portrayal on its head by addressing the concept of alienation:  “But the exercise of labour power…is the worker’s own life-activity, the manifestation of his own life.”  The process of selling one’s labor for a wage, or “in order to live”, remains fundamentally attached to the life-activity of the laborer as his “necessary means of subsistence.”[3]  The laborer, thus, remains alienated from his own life-activity because “he does not even reckon labor as part of his life.”  Instead of being seen as a critical element of one’s life, “life begins [for the laborer] where [his work] ceases, at table, in the public house, in bed.”[4]  While the laborer is at work, he is not living; while he is not at work, he thus is living.  This process of alienation removes the result of his actions, the commodities he produces, from his life entirely.  The products he makes at work are consciously removed from his life-activity in the same way that his work is consciously a sacrifice of his life.
                In order to relieve the notion that this form of transaction had occurred throughout history, Marx asserts that labor-power was not historically commodified.  In slavery for example, the power of the laborer is sold as the form of the slave itself.  It is a packaged deal, so-to-speak, in the same way that an ox is used for services by a peasant.  Serfdom as well is a partially-commodified form of labor, where the serf “sells only a part of his labour power” but “does not receive a wage from the owner of the land; rather the owner of the land receives a tribute from [the serf].”[5]  In this way, Marx has attributed commodified labor power as endemic to a specific set of social relations, those being between a capitalist and the possessor of labor power in a capitalist society, the worker.

                The process of commodity production through labor power in capitalism functions “only by co-operating in a certain way” where men “mutually exchange their activities.”  The relations that people enter into become the defining elements of their existence, which “are transformed with the change and development of the material means of production, the productive forces.”  In this way, Marx is able to categorize historical epochs by social relations and the material means of production that subsequently arise from these relations:  “Ancient society, feudal society, [and] bourgeois society.”  These material means of production are “totalities of production relations” which denote distinguishable and temporal “stages of development in the history of mankind.”[6]  Capital however, as a social relation and “bourgeois production relation,” breaks from previous forms by its inclusion of a value for exchange, or “exchange value.”
                Exchange values are a quantifiable “sum of commodities….of social magnitudes.”  In this way Capital differentiates itself from all other forms of commodities due to its dual nature:  it is made up of both utility, in the form of labor, instruments, and raw materials, as well as exchangeability in the form of a quantifiable relation to the totality of all other commodities (money, gold, or the ‘universal exchange equivalent’).  For Marx now, the only thing remaining to do is explain how Capital is produced.
                In the exchange between the worker and the capitalist, “the worker receives means of subsistence” while “the capitalist receives…the productive activity of the worker.”  This difference is critical because the worker “gives to the accumulated labour a greater value than it previously possessed”[7] because the value of the commodity produced includes the value needed to provide the worker (it’s use value) and the stored up-exchange value of the materials on which the laborer works.  The worker however, as we’ve seen, is paid a wage according to his means of subsistence, not to the value of what he has produced.  Whereas the worker receives a consumable commodity (the wage can be used, and then destroyed through consumption of products, food..etc), the capitalist receives an exchangeable commodity, which retains its value through exchange up until it is eventually consumed/destroyed.  

It is in this process directly that the concept of exploitation comes to the front.  The worker is exploited by the capitalist because of the deception of equal exchange in the process of capital production.  How does this deception take place?  Through formal contract.  The worker sells his labor according to an agreed upon wage, which takes place in the workplace.  The worker does this every day of his life up until the point that he ceases to work in the workplace.  The alienation of the workplace from “life-activity” provides the conscious explanation for exploitation, while the exchange relations between the capitalist and the laborer provide the material explanation for exploitation.  In this manner, we can see that the workplace contains the totality of these relations, both in their conscious and material forms.


[1] Marx, Wage Labor and Capital in Tucker Collection PDF, p. 244
[2] Ibid, 245
[3] Ibid
[4] Ibid, 246
[5] Ibid, 246
[6] Ibid, 248
[7] Ibid, 250

No comments:

Post a Comment